I Act Therefore I Live? Autopoiesis, Sensorimotor Autonomy, and Extended Agency
Main Article Content
Abstract
This paper aims to determine whether extended human-machine cognitive systems and group systems can be regarded as autonomous agents. For this purpose, I compare two notions of agency: one developed within analytical philosophy of action and based on the concept of intention, and the other introduced by enactivists via the concepts of autopoiesis and sensorimotor autonomy. I argue that only the latter approach can be used to demonstrate autonomous agency in respect of systems that are not humans as such, though they contain humans as their elements. After introducing Maturana and Varela’s conception of minimal autonomy as a kind of generalization of autopoiesis, I present the three conditions of agency put forward by Barandiaran, Di Paolo and Rohde, noting that they do not invoke the property of being alive as necessary in that respect. I argue that both extended and group systems can satisfy these conditions of agency, even though they are not alive as such. The fulfillment of these conditions, however, is ensured by the autopoietic nature of the living components of these systems. That being said, an autonomous system itself does not need to be alive in the biological sense. Sensorimotor, adaptive agency could emerge out of other processes than those responsible for biological life. The article concludes with a suggestion that this is exactly what will happen if an autonomous system is ever artificially created. It would be functionally indistinguishable from a living organism, though not alive in a biological sense.
Article Details
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.
By submitting his/her work to the Editorial Board, the author accepts, upon having his/her text recommended for publication, that Diametros applies the Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license to the works we publish. Under this license, authors agree to make articles legally available for reuse, without permission or fees. Anyone may read, download, copy, print, distribute or reuse these articles without asking prior permission from the publisher or the author, as long as the author and original source are properly cited. The author holds the copyright without any other restrictions. Full information about CC-BY: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/legalcode.
How to Cite
References
Adamatzky A., Komosinski M. (2009), Artificial Life Models in Software, Springer, London.
Barandiaran X. E. (2017), “Autonomy and Enactivism: Towards a Theory of Sensorimotor Autonomous Agency,” Topoi 36: 409-430.
Barandiaran X. E., Di Paolo E., Rohde M. (2009), “Defining Agency: Individuality, Normativity, Asymmetry, and Spatio-Temporality in Action,” Adaptive Behavior 17 (5): 367-386.
Beer R. D., Di Paolo E. A. (2023), “The Theoretical Foundations of Enaction: Precariousness,” Biosystems 223, 104823.
Chisholm R. (1976), “The Agent as Cause,” [in:] Action Theory, M. Brand, D. Walton (eds.), D. Reidel Publishing Co. Dordrecht: 199-211.
Chopra S., White L.F. (2011), A Legal Theory for Autonomous Artificial Agents, The University of Michigan Press, Michigan.
Clark A. (2008), Supersizing the Mind. Embodiment, Action and Cognitive Extension, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Clark A. (2010), “Coupling, Constitution and the Cognitive Kind: A Reply to Adams and Aizawa,” [in:] The Extended Mind, R. Menary (ed.), The MIT Press, Cambridge: 81-100.
Clark A., Chalmers D. (1998), “The Extended Mind,” Analysis 58 (1): 7-19.
Cummins F. (2014), “Agency is Distinct from Autonomy,” Avant V (2/2014): 98-112.
Davidson D. (1978), “Intending,” Philosophy of History and Action 11: 41-60.
Davidson D. (1982), “Rational Animals,” Dialectica 36 (4): 317-327.
De Jaegher H., Di Paolo E. (2007), “Participatory Sense-Making: An Enactive Approach to Social Cognition,” Phenomenology and the cognitive sciences 6: 485-507.
Dennett D. (1976), “Conditions of Personhood,” [in:] The Identities of Persons, A. Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), University of California Press, Berkeley: 175-196.
Di Paolo E. (2009), “Extended Life,” Topoi 28 (1): 9-21.
Di Paolo E., Thompson E. (2014), “The Enactive Approach,” [in:] The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition, L. Shapiro (ed.), Routledge, New York: 68-78.
Dworkin G. (1988), The Theory and Practice of Autonomy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Elder-Vass D. (2010), The Causal Power Or Social Structures. Emergence, Structure and Agency, Cambridge University Press, New York.
Elder-Vass D. (2014), “Social Entities and the Basis of Their Powers”, [in:] Rethinking the Individualism-Holism Debate. Essays in the Philosophy of Social Science, J. Zahle, F. Colin (eds.), Springer, Cham: 39-53.
Floridi L., Sanders J.W. (2004), “On the Morality of Artificial Agents,” Minds and Machines 14: 349-379.
Frankfurt H. (1971), “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,” The Journal of Philosophy 68: 5-20.
Froese T., Ziemke T. (2009), “Enactive Artificial Intelligence: Investigating the Systemic Organization of Life and Mind,” Journal of Artificial Intelligence 173: 466-500.
Goldspink Ch., Kay R. (2003), “Organizations as Self-Organizing and Sustaining Systems: A Complex and Autopoietic Systems Perspective,” International Journal of General Systems 32 (5): 459-474.
Heersmink R. (2012), “Mind and Artifact: A Multidimensional Matrix for Exploring Cognition-Artifact Relations,” [in:] Proceedings of the 5th AISB Symposium on Computing and Philosophy, M. Bishop, Y. Erden (eds.), Bath: 54-61.
Jonas H. (1968), “Biological Foundations of Individuality,” International Philosophical Quarterly 8: 231-251.
Kyselo M. (2014), “The Body Social: Enactive Approach to the Self,” Frontiers in Psychology 5: 1-16.
Luhmann N. (1986), “The Autopoiesis of Social Systems,” [in:] Sociocybernetic Paradoxes. F. Geyer, J. van der Zouwen (eds.), SAGE Publications, London: 172-192.
Luhmann N. (1995), Social Systems, Stanford University Press, Stanford.
Markosian N. (1999), “A Compatibilist Version of The Theory of Agent Causation,” Pacific philosophical quarterly 80: 257‑277.
Maturana H. (1987), “The Biological Foundations of Self-Consciousness and the Physical Domain of Existence,” [in:] Physics of Cognitive Processes, E. Caianiello (ed.), World Scientific, Singapore: 324–379.
Maturana H., Varela F. (1980), Autopoiesis and Cognition – the Realization of Human Understanding, Shambhala, Boston.
Maturana H., Varela F. (1992), The Tree of Knowledge—The Biological Roots of Human Understanding, Shambhala, Boston.
Mingers J. (2002), “Can Social System Be Autopoietic? Assessing Luhmann’s Social Theory,” Sociological Review 50 (2): 278-299.
Moreno A., Etxeberria A., Umerez J. (2008), “The Autonomy of Biological Individuals and Artificial Models,” BioSystems 91: 309–319.
Pattee H.H. (2001), “The Physics of Symbols: Bridging the Epistemic Cut,” BioSystems 60 (1/3): 5–21.
Rohde M., Steward J. (2008), “Ascriptional and ‘Genuine’ Autonomy,” BioSystems 91 (2): 424–433.
Russell S., Norvig P. (1995), Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach, Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs.
Sanches de Oliveira G., van Es T., Hipólito I. (2023), “Scientific Practice as Ecological-Enactive Co-Construction,” Synthese 202 (1): 1-33.
Thompson E. (2007), Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology and the Sciences of Mind, Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
Thompson E., Stapleton M. (2009), “Making Sense of Sense-Making: Reflections on Enactive and Extended Mind Theories,” Topoi 28 (1): 23–30.
Varela F. (1979), Principles of Biological Autonomy, North Holland Publishing, New York.
Varela F. (1991), “Organism: A Meshwork of Selfless Selves,” [in:] Organisms and the Origins of Self, A. I. Tauber (ed.), Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht: 79-107.
Varela F., Thompson E., Rosch E. (1991), The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience, MIT Press, Cambridge.