The Logical Structure of Intentional Anonymity
Main Article Content
Abstract
It has been noticed by several authors that the colloquial understanding of anonymity as mere unknownness is insufficient. This common sense notion of anonymity does not recognize the role of the goal for which the anonymity is sought. Starting with the distinction between intentional and unintentional anonymity (which are usually taken to be the same) and the general concept of the non-coordinatability of traits, we offer a logical analysis of anonymity and identification (understood as de-anonymization). In our enquiry, we focus on the intentional aspect of anonymity and develop a metaphor of an “anonymity game” between “perpetrator” and “detective”. Starting from common sense intuitions, we provide a formalized, critical notion of anonymity.
Article Details
By submitting his/her work to the Editorial Board, the author accepts, upon having his/her text recommended for publication, that Diametros applies the Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) license to the works we publish. Under this license, authors agree to make articles legally available for reuse, without permission or fees. Anyone may read, download, copy, print, distribute or reuse these articles without asking prior permission from the publisher or the author, as long as the author and original source are properly cited. The author holds the copyright without any other restrictions. Full information about CC-BY: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/legalcode.
How to Cite
References
Anscombe G.E. (1957), Intention, Blackwell, Oxford.
Boer S.E., Lycan W.G. (1975). “Knowing Who,” Philosophical Studies 28 (5): 299–344. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00381575
Davidson D. (1980), Actions and Events, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Dennett D. (1982), “Beyond Belief,” [in:] Thought and Object, A. Woodfield (ed), Clarendon, Oxford.
Donnellan K. (1966), “Reference and Definite Descriptions,” Philosophical Review 75: 281–304. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2183143
Forsyth F. (1971), The Day of the Jackal, The Viking Press, New York.
Frankfurt H. (1978), “The Problem of Action,” American Philosophical Quarterly 15: 157–162.
Kaplan D. (1968), “Quantifying In,” Synthese 19 (1–2): 178–214. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00568057
Matthews S. (2010), “Anonymity and the Social Self,” American Philosophical Quarterly 47: 351–363.
Nissenbaum H. (1999), “The Meaning of Anonymity in an Information Age,” The Information Society 15: 141–144. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/019722499128592
Ohm P. (2010), “Broken Promises of Privacy: Responding to the Surprising Failure of Anonymization,” UCLA Law Review 57: 1701–1777.
Ponesse J. (2013), “Navigating the Unknown: Towards a Positive Conception of Anonymity,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (3): 320–344. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/sjp.12035
Quine W.V. (1956), “Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes,” Journal of Philosophy 53 (5): 177–187. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2022451
Sajjad T. (2013), Transitional Justice in South Asia: A Study of Afghanistan and Nepal, Routledge, London and New York. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203431375
Sosa E. (1970), “Propositional Attitudes De Dicto and De Re,” Journal of Philosophy 67 (21): 883–896. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2024040
Wallace K.A. (1999), “Anonymity,” Ethics and Information Technology 1 (1): 23–35. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1010066509278